gugagore 13 hours ago

FYI the use of "subtype" here does not, as far as I know, have much connection to the concept in class-based object oriented programming languages.

https://lean-lang.org/doc/reference/latest/Basic-Types/Subty...

A crucial difference between type theory (as its known in Lean) and set theory is that an inhabitant/element is of exactly one type.

  • ImprobableTruth 6 hours ago

    Caveat: Coercions exist in Lean, so subtypes actually can be used like the supertype, similar to other languages. This is done via essentially adding an implicit casting operation when such a usage is encountered.

  • codethief 11 hours ago

    I'm not quite following. According to the OP and the docs you linked, a subtype is defined by a base type and a predicate. In other words: You can view it as a subset of the set of elements of the base type. That's pretty much the standard definition of a subtype.

    Object-oriented programming languages are not that different: The types induced by classes can easily be viewed as sets: A child class is a specialized version of its parent's class, hence a subtype/subset thereof if you define all the sets by declaring `instanceof` to be their predicate function.

    • SkiFire13 10 hours ago

      > You can view it as a subset of the set of elements of the base type.

      Technically speaking the elements in the supertype are all distinct from the elements in the subtype and viceversa. They are not a subset of the other, hence why it's improper to consider one a subtype of the other.

CSMastermind 4 hours ago

I've been meaning to learn Lean and fascinated with the concept but syntax like:

    let rec helperMemo : Nat → HashMap Nat Nat → Nat × HashMap Nat Nat
is a big turnoff to me. I find it annoying to parse mentally. I can do it but I have to concentrate or it's easy to gloss over an important detail.
  • tikhonj 39 minutes ago

    What makes it hard to parse? The lack of parentheses? The way HashMap Nat Nat is a bit verbose and not clear at a glance? Something else?

  • westurner 4 hours ago

    Does aliasing the types work?

      def MemoMap := HashMap Nat Nat
      def MemoResult := Nat × MemoMap
    
      let rec helperMemo : Nat → MemoMap → MemoResult
    • tossandthrow 4 hours ago

      Record types would likely help a lot also.

      Tupples don't really indicate what I can expect from the members.

jeremyscanvic 12 hours ago

Really interesting trick!

  • thaumasiotes 4 hours ago

    He doesn't mention it, but this is a form of proof by induction. (As you'd expect, really, for a universal statement.)

    Induction is often taught as something you do with natural numbers. But it's actually something you do with sets that are defined inductively. Any time you have a set that is defined like so:

        1. x is in the set.
    
        2. for all y in the set, f(y) is in the set
    
    (where x and f are constants), you can apply induction. The base case is that you show some property is true of x. The inductive step is that you show that when the property is true of y, it is necessarily true of f(y).

    If you have multiple elements that you guarantee will be in the set, each of them must be dealt with as a base case, and if you have multiple rules generating new elements from existing ones, each of them must be dealt with as another inductive step.

    For the case of the natural numbers, x is 0, and f is the successor function.

    If you wanted to apply this model to the Fibonacci sequence, you could say that the tuple (0, 1, 1) is in the set [representing the idea "F_1 is 1"] and provide the generator f((a, b, c)) = (b, a+b, c+1). Then since (0, 1, 1) is in the set, so is (1, 1, 2) [or "F_2 is 1"], and then (1, 2, 3) ["F_3 is 2"], and so on.

    (Or you could say that the two tuples (1, 1) and (2, 1) are both in the set, and provide the generator f( (i, x), (i+1, y) ) = (i+2, x+y). Now your elements are simpler, your generator is more complex, and your set has exactly the same structure as before.)

    The approach taken by the author's "improved solution" is to define a set consisting of the elements of the memoization table, with the generator being the function chain that adds elements to the table. He annotates the type of the elements to note that they must be correct (this annotation is administrative, just making it easy to describe what it is that we want to prove), and then does a proof over the addition operation that this correctness is preserved (the inductive step!).

almostgotcaught 12 hours ago

This is proof by exhaustion: the "proof" just computes the entire memo table for any n and compares the values in the table with the corresponding return from recursive definition. You could write this same proof in absolutely any language that supports recursion (or not, if you transform to the bottom-up formulation).

  • lacker 10 hours ago

    In Lean you don't actually have to run this for every n to verify that the algorithm is correct for every n. Correctness is proved at type-checking time, without actually running the algorithm. That's something that you can't do in a normal programming language.

    • almostgotcaught 9 hours ago

      it's explicitly stated in the article:

      > For an arbitrary n, compute the table full of values and their proofs, and just pull out the nth proof

      if you thought harder about it you'd realize what you're suggesting is impossible

      • lacker 9 hours ago

        It's not impossible, that's the whole point of a theorem prover. You write a computation, but you don't actually have to run the computation. Simply typechecking the computation is enough to prove that its result is correct.

        For example, in a theorem prover, you can write an inductive proof that x^2 + x is even for all x. And you can write this via a computation that demonstrates that it's true for zero, and if it's true for x, then it's true for x + 1. However, you don't need to run this computation in order to prove that it's true for large x. That would be computationally intractable, but that's okay. You just have to typecheck to get a proof.

        • almostgotcaught 9 hours ago

          > you can write an inductive proof that x^2 * (x^2 - 1) is divisible by 4 for all x

          my friend you should either read the article more closely or think harder. he's not proving that the recurrence relation is correct (that would be meaningless - a recurrence relation is just given), he's proving that DP/memoization computes the same values as the recurrence relation.

          the obvious indicator is that no property of any numbers is checked here - just that one function agrees with another:

            theorem maxDollars_spec_correct : ∀ n, maxDollars n = maxDollars_spec n
          
          this is the part that's undecidable (i should've said that instead of "impossible")

          https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Richardson%27s_theorem

          • thaumasiotes 5 hours ago

            > my friend you should either read the article more closely or think harder

            Hmmm.

            > no property of any numbers is checked here - just that one function agrees with another:

                theorem maxDollars_spec_correct : ∀ n, maxDollars n = maxDollars_spec n
            
            > this is the part that's undecidable (i should've said that instead of "impossible")

            > https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Richardson%27s_theorem

            Given that both `maxDollars n` and `maxDollars_spec n` are defined to be natural numbers, I'm not sure why Richardson's theorem is supposed to be relevant.

            But even if it was, the structure of the proof is to produce the fact `maxDollars_spec n = maxDollars n` algebraically from a definition, and then apply the fact that equality is symmetric to conclude that `maxDollars n = maxDollars_spec n`. And once again I'm not sure how you could possibly fail to conclude that two quantities are equal after being given the fact that they're equal.

  • hansvm 7 hours ago

    That can't possibly be the case. The thing concluded was that for every n the statement holds. To do that exhaustively for _every_ n requires infinite time. Either their conclusion is incorrect, or your description of the proof is incorrect.

  • SkiFire13 9 hours ago

    > the "proof" just computes the entire memo table for any n

    No, this is what would happen _if you ran the proof_, but proofs are not meant to be ran in the first place! The usual goal is proving their correctness, and for that it's enough for them to _typecheck_.

    • almostgotcaught 9 hours ago

      it's explicitly stated in the article:

      > For an arbitrary n, compute the table full of values and their proofs, and just pull out the nth proof

      if you thought harder about it you'd realize what you're suggesting is impossible

      • ImprobableTruth 6 hours ago

        This is the fault of sloppy language. In Lean, _proofs_ (equivalent to functions) and _proof objects/certificates_ (values) need to be distinguished. You can't compute proofs, only proof objects. In the above quote, replace "proof" with "certificate" and you'll see that it's a perfectly valid (if trivial - it essentially just applies a lemma) proof.

        • almostgotcaught 6 hours ago

          a distinction without a difference wrt what i'm pointing out: this proof uses exactly zero mathematics just effectively checks all the values of maxDollars_spec.

  • Quekid5 12 hours ago

    Not if that language doesn't actually check the totality of your proof and ensures that the base case holds.

    • almostgotcaught 12 hours ago

      i don't know what you're saying - here is the proof that is described in the article:

      1. build a table tab[n]

      2. check that for every i, tab[i] == maxDollars_spec[i]

      if you take the latter approach i proposed (bottom up) there is nothing to check the totality of.

xnacly 11 hours ago

sigma types, hmmm